This is a technical chapter, where we prove that there really are integrals: by giving a precise construction that satisfies the axioms!
We have introduced axioms for integration, and gotten a bit comfortable using these axioms to compute things. For example, in the last chapter we proved the following facts with relatively straightforward arguments:
- If is integrable and bounded, then is continuous.
- If is integrable then
- If is integrable then
These theorems all are of the same form: they’re conditional on if an integral exists, then we know stuff about it. This of course is kind of disappointing: but also to be expected: we’ve given the axioms for an integral but we haven’t shown anything actually satisfies these axioms yet! This chapter fills this gap, by recalling our natural candidate for an integral, and then proving it actually does satisfy the axioms. The arguments are all very reminiscent of the calculations we did for and but more abstract, and while straightforward they will not be a focus of ours, here at the end of the course. This is a great chapter to read if you’re the kind of mathematician who has been nervously following the work in the previous chapter / final homework, worrying that maybe its all for nothing because maybe integrals don’t exist at all! But if this hasn’t been a big worry of yours, you’ll miss nothing by skipping over this chapter.
We recall first the definition of the Darboux Integral. Let be a function on the closed interval , and write and for the upper and lower sums, with and for any partition . Then is Darboux-Integrable on if , and we define the integral to be this common value: . We will prove that this definition satisfies the axioms: that is,
For every then is Darboux integrable for any interval and
If are Darboux integrable on and for all then
If is an interval and , then is Darboux integrable if and only if it is Darboux integrable on both and . Furthermore, in this case their values are related by .
The proof takes place in several steps, but we begin by developing a basic theory of partitions of intervals, which are the crucial defining features of our sum.
Working with Partitions
Definition 26.1 (Partitions) A partition of the interval is a finite ordered set with .
- is called the length of the partition
- We write for the interval of , and for its width.
- The maxwidth of is the maximal width of the ’s intervals, .
- The set of all partitions on a fixed interval is denoted .
The goal of this section is to prove the seemingly obvious fact . This takes more work than it seems at first because of the definitions of as a supremum and as an infimum, but proves an invaluable tool in analyzing integrability.
Definition 26.2 (Refining Partitions) A partition is a refinement of a partition if contains all the points of (that is, ).
Proposition 26.1 (The Refinement Lemma) If is a refinement of the partition on a closed interval , then for any bounded function the following inequalities hold
Proof. Here we give the argument for lower sums, the analogous case for upper sums is asked in Exercise 26.1. Since and both are finite sets we know contains finitely many more points than . Here we will show that if contains exactly one more point than , that the claim holds; the general case follows by induction.
In this case we may write , where lies within the partition . Thus, for the left half after subdivision, and for the right half. Outside of , the two partitions are identical, so their difference is given only by the difference of their values on :
Since both and are subsets of , the infimum over each of them is at its smallest the infimum over the whole set. This implies
Thus, the first term in the difference above is bigger than the second, so the overall difference is positive. Thus and so as claimed,
Exercise 26.1 Following the structure above, prove that if refines , that
Proposition 26.2 (Upper/Lower Sum Inequality) Lower sums are always smaller than upper sums, independent of partition. That is, if be two arbitrary partitions of a closed interval , for any bounded function ,
Proof. Let and be two arbitrary partitions of the interval , and consider the partition . This contains both and as subsets, so is a common refinement of both.
Using our previous work, this implies
We also know that for the partition itself,
Taken together these produce the the string of inequalities
From which immediately follows that , as desired.
Proposition 26.3 (Upper/Lower Integral Inequality) Let be any closed interval and a bounded function on . Then the lower integral is less than or equal to the upper integral,
Proof. Recall that is the infimum over all partitions of the upper sums.
Let be an arbitrary partition. By ?prp-upper-lower-on-different-partitions we know the upper sum with respect to any partition whatsoever is greater than or equal to , so is a lower bound for the set of all upper sums.
Thus, the infimum of the upper sums - the greatest of all lower bounds - must be at greater or equal to this specific lower bound,
But this holds for every partition . That means this number is actually an upper bound for the set of all . And so, it must be greater than or equal to the least upper bound :
Corollary 26.1 To show a function is integrable, it suffices to show that .
(To see this, recall in general that from ?prp-lower-int-leq-upper-int. So, if then in fact they are equal, which is the definition of being integrable.)
Integrability Criteria
Here we prove a very useful condition to test if a function is integrable, by finding sufficient partitions.
Theorem 26.1 Let be a bounded function on a closed interval . Then is integrable if for every there exists a partition of such that
Here we prove one direction of this theorem, namely that if such partitions exist for all then is integrable. We prove the converse below.
Proof. Let , and assume there is a partition with Then, recalling and by definition, we chain these together with to get
Thus, the interval is contained within the interval which has length . Thus its length must also be less than :
But was arbitrary! Thus the only possibility is that , and so the two are equal, meaning is integrable as claimed.
Now we prove the second direction of Theorem 26.1: the proof is reminiscent of the triangle inequality, though without absolute values (as we know terms of the form are always nonnegative already)
Proof. Assume that is integrable, so . Since is the greatest lower bound of all the upper sums, for any , is not a lower bound: that is, there must be some partition where
Similarly, since is the least upper bound of the lower sums, there must be some partition with
Now, define to be the common refinement of these two partitions, and observe that
Where the last inequality uses . Thus, for our arbitrary we found a partition on which the upper and lower sums differ by less than that, as claimed.
And finally, we provide an even stronger theorem than -integrability, that lets us prove a function is integrable and calculate the resulting value, by taking the limit of carefully chosen sequences of partitions. More precisely, we want to consider any sequence of partitions that’s getting finer and finer:
Definition 26.3 (Shrinking Partitions) A sequence of partitions is said to be shrinking if the corresponding sequence of max-widths converges to .
We often abbreviate the phrase is a shrinking sequence of partitions by .
Theorem 26.2 (Integrability & Shrinking Partitions) Let be a function on the interval , and assume that are two sequences of shrinking partitions such that Then, is integrable on and is equal to this common value.
Proof. Call this common limiting value . As is defined as a supremum over all lower sums
Similiarly, as is the infimum over all upper sums, we have
By ?prp-lower-int-leq-upper-int we know , which allows us to string these inequalities together:
Under the assumption that these two limits are equal, all four quantities in this sequence must be equal, and in particular . Thus is integrable, and its value coincides with the limit of either of these sequences of shrinking partitions, as claimed.
Verification of Axioms
With these tools in hand we verify the axioms of integration hold for the Darboux integral. For readability, we write instead of throughout.
Proposition 26.4 (Integrability of Constants) Let be a constant function, and an interval. Then is Darboux integrable on and
Proof. For any partition , we have as is constant. Thus, The upper and lower sums are constant, independent of partition, and so their respective infima/suprema are also constant, equal to this same value. Thus is integrable, and the integral is also this common value
Proposition 26.5 (Integration and Inequalities) Let be Darboux integrable functions on and assume that for all . Then
Proof. The constraint implies that on any partition we have Or, equivalently . Taking the supremum over all of this set of nonnegative numbers yields a nonnegative number, so
But since we’ve assumed and are integrable we know that and . Thus
Proposition 26.6 (Integration and Subdivision) Let be an interval and . Then a function defined on is Darboux-integrable on this interval if and only if it is Darboux integrable on both and . Furthermore, when defined these three integrals satisfy the identity
Proof. First, assume that is integrable on . By ?thm-epsilon-integrability, this means for any there exists a partition where . Now consider the refinement . By the refinement lemma, Thus as well. Next we take this partition and divide it into partitions of each subinterval and . By simply re-grouping the finite sums, we see
And, by the definitions of upper and lower sums, for each we know . All that remains to insure the integrability of on and is to show that these differences are individually less than . But this is immediate, as for example,
and the same argument applies to .
Next we assume integrability on the two subintervals, and prove integrability on the whole interval.
Proof. Let and by our integrability assumptions choose partitions of and of such that Now, their union is a partition of , and re-grouping the finite sums, we see
Thus,
So, we see that integrability on is equivalent to integrability on and . Finally, we need to show in the case where all three integrals are defined, the subdivision equality actually holds.
Proof. Let be any partition of the interval and define the usual suspects: We need three pieces of data. First, the inequalities relating integrals to upper and lower sums Second, the inequalities of refinements: and third, the relationships between and :
Putting all of these together, we get both lower and upper estimates for the sum of the integrals over the subdivision:
And concatenating these inequalities gives the overall bound, for any arbitrary partition :
Thus, the sum of these integrals lies between the upper and lower sum of on for every partition. As is integrable, we know there is a single number with this property, and that number is by definition the integral. Thus
Phew! We’ve successfully verified all three axioms for the Darboux integral. Taken together, these prove that our construction really is an integral!
Corollary 26.2 The equality of upper and lower sums satisfies the axioms of integration, and thus the Darboux Integral really does define an integral.